Skip to content

Intuitions about case selection are often wrong

Last updated on September 6, 2017

Imagine the following simple setup: there are two switches (X and Z) and a lamp (Y). Both switches and the lamp are ‘On’. You want to know what switch X does, but you have only one try to manipulate the switches. Which one would you choose to switch off: X, Z or it doesn’t matter?

These are the results of the quick Twitter poll I did on the question:

Clearly, almost half of the respondents think it doesn’t matter, switching X is the second choice, and only 2 out of 15 would switch Z to learn what X does. Yet, it is by pressing Z that we have the best chance of learning something about the effect of X. This seems quite counter-intuitive, so let me explain.

First, let’s clarify the assumptions embedded in the setup: (A1) both switches and the lamp can be either ‘On’ [1 ] or ‘Off’ [0]; (A2) the lamp is controlled only by these switches; there is nothing outside the system that controls its output; (A3) X and Z can work individually or in combination (so that the lamp is ‘On’ only if both switches are ‘On’ simultaneously).

Now let’s represent the information we have in a table:

Switch X Switch Z Lamp Y
1 1 1
0 0 0

We are allowed to make one experiment in the setup (press only one switch). In other words, we can add an observation for one more row of the table. Which one should it be?

Well, let’s see what happens if we switch off X (let’s call this strategy S1). There are two possible outcomes: either the lamp goes off (S1a) or it stays on (S1b).

In the first case (represented as the second line in the table below) we can conclude that X is not necessary for the lamp to be ‘On’, but we do not know whether X can switch on the lamp on its own (whether it is sufficient to do so).

Switch X Switch Z Lamp Y
1 1 1
0 1 1
0 0 0

If the lamp goes off when we press X, we know that X is necessary for the outcome but we do not know whether X can turn on the lamp on its own or only in combination with Z.

Switch X Switch Z Lamp Y
1 1 1
0 1 0
0 0 0

To sum up, by pressing X we learn either that (S1a) X is not necessary or that (S1b) X matters but we do not know whether on its own or only in combination with Z.

 

Now, let’s see what happens if we press Z (strategy S2). Again either the lamp stays on (S2a) or it goes off (S2b).

Under the first scenario, we learn that X is sufficient to turn on the lamp.

Switch X Switch Z Lamp Y
1 1 1
1 0 1
0 0 0

Under the second scenario, we learn that X is not sufficient to turn on the light. It is still possible that it is necessary for turning on the lamp in combination with Z.

Switch X Switch Z Lamp Y
1 1 1
1 0 0
0 0 0

To sum up, by pressing Z we learn either that (S2a) X can turn on the lamp or (S2b) that it cannot turn on the lamp on its own but is possibly necessary in combination with Z. 

Comparing the two sets of inferences, I think it is clear that the second one is much more informative. By pressing Z we learn either that we can turn on the lamp by pressing X or that we cannot unless Z is ‘On’. By pressing X we learn next to nothing: we are either still in the dark whether X works on its own to turn on the lamp (sorry for the pun) or that X matters but we still do now know whether we also need Z to be ‘On’.

If you are still unconvinced, the following table summarizes all inferences under all strategies and contingencies about each of the possible effects (X, Z, and the interaction XZ):

X works on its own Z works on its own Only XZ works Strategy
? True False S1a
? False ? S1b
True ? False S2a
False ? ? S2b

It should be obvious now that we are better off by pressing Z to learn about the effect of X.

Good, but what’s the relevance of this little game? Well, the game resembles a research design situation in which we have one observation (case), we have the resources to add only one more, and we have to select which observation to make. In other words, the game is about case selection.

For example, we observe a case with a rare outcome – say, successful regional integration. We suspect that two factors are at play, both of which are present in the case – say, high trade volume within the integrating block and democratic form of government for all units. And we wanna probe the effect of trade volume in particular. In that case, the analysis above suggests that we should choose a case that has the same volume of trade but a non-democratic form of government, rather than a case which has low volume of trade and democratic form of government.

This result is counter-intuitive, so let’s spell out why. First, note that we are interested in the effect of X (the effect of the switch and of trade volume) and not in explaining Y (how to turn on the lamp or how does regional integration come about). This is a subtle difference in interpretation, but one that is crucial for the analysis. Second, note that we are more interested in the effect of X than in the effect of Z, although both are potential causes of Y. If both X and Z are of equal interest, then obviously it doesn’t matter which one observation we make. Third, the result hinges on the assumption that there is nothing other than X or Z (or their interaction) that matters for Y. Once we admit other possible causal variables in the set-up, then we are no longer better off switching Z to learn the effect of X.

Sooooo, don’t take this little game as general advice on case selection. But it definitely shows that when it comes to research design our intuitions cannot always be trusted.

P.S. One assumption on which the analysis does not depend is binary effects and outcomes: it works equally well with probabilistic effects that are additive or multiplicative (involving an interaction). 

Learn more about research design.

Published inComparative research and configurational methods

Be First to Comment

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published.